Discussion about this post

User's avatar
Jessica Hullman's avatar

This paper has a nice explication of how different strictly proper scoring rules imply different expectations about the kinds of decisions one will face

https://www.cambridge.org/core/services/aop-cambridge-core/content/view/1CE00C0166746CF143388CCDF7926A3A/S0031824800009910a.pdf/pragmatists_guide_to_epistemic_utility.pdf

Expand full comment
Roman W 🇵🇱🇺🇦's avatar

"Suppose you have a model predicting that the event happens with probability Q. How much of your pot should you bet? You could just maximize the expected value of your return. "

There is more than one subtlety here, as those of us who learned or practiced quantitative finance know :)

Subtlety 1: the time value of money. If the payout happens in a year's time, getting paid 1 dollar then is worth less to me now, because of interest rates being non-zero. If the substance of your bet is not connected to interest rates, this is irrelevant, but it becomes relevant if, for example, you're betting on Fed not raising interest rates to 20%.

Subtlety 2 (related to Subtlety 1): Different payoffs related to a bet on a world-changing event happen in different states of the world. Take an extreme example: a bet on a world-ending nuclear war (WENW) happening within 1 year. If I bet on "there will be such a war" and win the bet, the payoff - if I live to receive it - will be worth 0. Hence, it doesn't make sense to bet on the nuclear war happening. Only betting against it can have a positive expected value. You can still work out some information about my estimate of the probability of WENW by proposing the odds B and asking me if I want to bet or not. But in the general case, where the value of the payoff to me conditioned on the resolution on the bet is unknown to you (as it often is), you'll find it hard to work out what my Q is.

This is known in financial literature as the difference between risk-neutral and real-world probabilities.

Expand full comment
14 more comments...

No posts